Necessity in Mīmāṃsā philosophy

Anand Vaidya has recently raised a very intriguing discussion on modality in Indian philosophy. His post started with the suggestion that modality is less central in Indian philosophy than it is in Western thought. In the comments, several scholars suggested examples hinting at reflections on modality also in Indian thought but, now that I think again about them, they mostly discussed the modality of possibility in Indian thought. What about necessity?

Mark Siderits, in his Nyāya Realism, Buddhist Critique (in The Empirical and the Transcendental, edited by Bina Gupta), mentions without further elaboration that Nyāya philosophers were “innocent of the notion of necessity” (p. 223). I think he is making or hinting at a valid point, in the sense that realist schools like Nyāya are much less inclined than Buddhist Pramāṇavāda to stress the need of logical necessity. In other words, Buddhist Pramāṇavādins will stress points such as the fact that the coexistence of (seemingly) conflicting characteristics in the same entity is logically impossible and that, consequently, the existence of atoms (which should be basic units but also extended in space) is impossible and that the non-existence of atoms is therefore a logical necessity.
By contrast, realist authors are much more committed to the existence of what sense perception attests to and would thus not subscribe to the idea that the lack of logical consistency can cause one to deny the existence of what we experience in the world. This is even more true in the case of Mīmāṃsā, since Mīmāṃsā authors are programmatically committed to worldly experience (lokavyavahāra). Thus, it is hardly the case that Mīmāṃsā authors will ever speak of logical necessity as contradicting worldly experience. Worldly experience is the primary instrument of knowledge (pramāṇa) and it cannot be contradicted because of purely logical reasons. By contrast, if there seems to be logical reasons contradicting our sense perception, it is our logical reasons which need reconsidering since they have probably led to a fallacy.
Moreover, the principle of self validity (svataḥ prāmāṇya) basically makes data count as if they were necessarily true, unless and until they are contradicted by a later, more precise, cognition.

Comments and discussions are welcome. Be sure you are making a point and contributing to the discussion.

Leave a Reply to Anand Vaidya Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

2 thoughts on “Necessity in Mīmāṃsā philosophy

  1. Dear Elisa

    Thanks for the fascinating post. And for pointing out the attention to the gap between cases of possibility and necessity I would like to follow up on the Nyāya and Mīmāṃsā material on necessity with you. I have now been given a paper by B.K. Matilal on necessity in Indian philosophy, the paper has several examples that are important. My general goal now is to compile a large set of examples and use them to address the other questions I asked in my post, such as what mechanisms are used for knowledge of necessity and possibility. I also wanted to suggest that my own reading of many of the schools of Indian philosophy is that necessity and possibility are in play in vary important ways, it is just that the ways in which they are in play are not the typical ways we see in Western philosophy. I will have more to say on this as I continue my research on this topic.

    Thanks again

    • Thanks to you, Anand! What paper is it?
      Although I am not an expert on the topic, I would agree with you on your conclusion and I look forward for reading your work about it.